MetisĀ asĀ subak. The traditional Balinese irrigation system for rice farmers. / Wikimedia Commons
By Lou Keep / 01.02.2018
Friedrich Nietzsche was most famously concerned with the problem of nihilism. All societies, in his view, rely on implicit value judgments. If the foundations of these are lost, he predicts terrible consequences: widespread apathy or violent, fanatical attempts to reclaim a sense of purpose, or perhaps both. We talk about values a lot, and we know they doĀ something, but we have little idea how. Compounding this is uncertainty over their loss. Nihilism is not a choice or intellectual commitment, but a thing that comes upon you. As Nietzsche put it in 1885: āNihilism stands at the door. Whence comes this uncanniest of all guests?ā
Part of the answer comes from understanding how values connect to knowledge and action. InĀ Seeing Like a StateĀ (1998),Ā the political scientist James C Scott classifies knowledge in two ways: epistemic knowledge, which can be quantified, theorised and transmitted in abstract, andĀ metisĀ (from the classical Greek), which concerns knowledge gained from practical experience, such as personal relationships, traditions, habits and psychological states.Ā MetisĀ governs local experience: farming the familyās land, for example, rather than agronomic study. We all recognise it; itās why we hire for experience. For instance, Jane and Martha have identical diplomas, but if Janeās first shift was on Tuesday and Marthaās was in 1970, then Martha will have certain tricks and habits to expedite her work. Still, itās not easy to quantify just what that is: Martha hasĀ metis, andĀ metisĀ canāt easily be reproduced. If it were trainable, it would have been in Janeās training.
Scottās genius is to compareĀ metisĀ to local traditions. Over a long enough time, habits and behaviours are selected for and passed down, just as evolution selects helpful traits. A successful group will institutionalise an irreducibly complex set of cultural tools that relate to its environment. Since these areĀ metis, and not epistemic, they wonāt always be obvious or quantifiable. Scott recounts dozens of examples of customs that might appear backwards, confused, unscientific ā yet when theyāre banned or discouraged, productivity collapses. He calls this the problem of ālegibilityā.
Epistemic theories rely on isolated, abstracted environments capable of taxonomy, but these are far removed from the dynamic, interconnected systems of nature and human culture.Ā Metis, by contrast, develops within complex, āillegibleā environments, and thus works with them. But that also means its application is limited to a specific act, rather than a broader theory. Outsiders want to know why something works, but locals will explain it in a language unintelligible to them.
These practices and traditions are, of course, more than work experience. Theyāre used to efficiently solve political problems. InĀ The Righteous Mind(2012), the social psychologist Jonathan Haidt describes Balinese rice farmers who needed to coordinate irrigation along a river. Since they were politically divided into small familial units ā calledĀ subaksĀ ā they needed to rely on means older than governance to ensure cooperation:
The ingenious religious solution to this problem of social engineering was to place a small temple at every fork in the irrigation system. The god in each such temple united all theĀ subaksĀ that were downstream from it into a community that worshipped that god, thereby helping theĀ subaksĀ to resolve their disputes more amicably. This arrangement minimised the cheating and deception that would otherwise flourish in a zero-sum division of water. The system made it possible for thousands of farmers, spread over hundreds of square kilometres, to cooperate without the need for central government, inspectors and courts.
This still occurs. A 2017Ā paperĀ by the economists Nathan Nunn of Harvard University and Raul Sanchez de la Sierra of the University of California, Berkeley mentionsĀ gri-gri, a magical powder that witchdoctors manufacture. In 2012, following a period of widespread banditry and state insecurity in the Democratic Republic of the Congo,Ā gri-griĀ came to a village elder in a dream. Applying this powder made the user bulletproof, and it worked so well that neighbouring communities swiftly adopted it. The reason was simple: groups fight better than individuals, and more people will dare to fight if they believe they are bulletproof. Hence, a village usingĀ gri-griĀ was more likely to survive.
Gri-griĀ and water temples are kinds ofĀ metis, but they require belief in larger structures: respectively, magic and gods. However these structures first developed, itās critical that they rest on more than mere faith or tradition. Shared values provide conviction for greater actions, but those values are certified by the success of those actions.Ā Gri-griās success is an empirical testament to magic, and its utility inclines one towards trusting more activities by witchdoctors. Nunn and Sanchez de la Sierra point out that
many of [the spells] appear to provide individuals with a greater sense of security and confidence, which could serve to ⦠reduce their anxiety and thus improve their performance. For example, most of the spells provide protection, whether it be from drought, disease, attacks on the village or even to harm potential thieves ā and thieves also believe in their efficacy, which acts as a deterrent.
In other words: these practices and institutions serve several different roles, all bound up in one another. This intermingling exacerbates the problem of legibility.
When we discuss changing values, we often think top-down: a new and persuasive ideology that took hold for intellectual reasons. What Scott and the adoption ofĀ gri-griĀ suggest is the opposite: the motive force of values requires a degree of certainty that is dependent on action. It wasĀ gri-griās empirical demonstration that allowed it spread it to neighbouring villages, not its poetry. The inverse to this is also important: we can improve on a specific task, but other roles need time to sediment and evolve. Trade the temples for a government, and you have zero-sum bickering. Explain the game theory behindĀ gri-gri, and no one will fight with it. The utility of a cultural institution first allows adoption, but its maintenance allowsĀ metisample time to tinker and perfect.
If weāve lost faith in certain values, then I doubt this was because of academic debates. The 20th century profoundly changed labour, technology and social organisation in the Western world. Itās hard to imagine that this didnāt changeĀ metis, or render older forms ofĀ metisĀ irrelevant. While the values ofĀ metisĀ might still be desired ā or even identified with ā they lack the same certainty they once had. Nothing can prove them and thus justify the higher claims. āFaith without works is dead,ā as the Bible said, but faith withoutĀ metisis unbelievable.
A top-down view of value implies that we can simply create new reasons for living, that the ideology itself is its own proof. But if values come bottom-up, then manās quest for meaning cannot be separated from his labour. They are the same.
Originally published by Aeon under a Creative Commons Attribution-No Derivatives license.